COUTO, Cristiano Pinheiro de Paula. 2014. Interview with
Dominick LaCapra. Intellectual History
Review, Volume 24, Issue 2, 2014, pp. 239-237.
Volume 24, Number 2 of the Intellectual History Review contains an interview with Dominick LaCapra,
conducted by Cristiano Pinheiro de Paula Couto back in 2012. Professor LaCapra
discussed several aspects of his voluminous work, marked by a persistent
willingness to investigate the boundaries between history and other
disciplines.
Here is a link to the
interview. I selected some quotes:
On the possibility of a (in Couto’s words) “dialogue
with the dead”, disagreeing with Sebald’s claim that “only in literature […] can
there be an attempt at restitution over and above the mere recital of facts,
and over and above scholarship”:
“History at some level is always a dialogue
with the dead, but the dialogue may be mostly like a monologue when it is
restricted to empirical research and reporting the facts with a kind of antiseptic
analysis of the facts, that’s when the dialogue becomes most like a monologue, us
talking about the dead as something we understand only in narrowly objective
terms. But it is possible for history to be at least comparable to literature
when it has other dimensions, such as the dimension of the elegy, awareness of
political assumptions and effects, and possible implications for the future. To
the extent that history has these other performative, ethical, and political dimensions,
it is also in essence an “attempt at restitution” – not necessarily redemption
but you are in a way bringing back the past and its dead and finding them to be
still living in a way that has an impact on how people live today and shape the
future.” (241)
Intellectual historians as intellectuals:
“The intellectuals in the United States who
tend to be most influential are people who are directly engaged in government
and in political processes, as well as people who are in some sense affiliated
with corporations.” But this is rarely the case with intellectual historians: “I
think the role of people like intellectual historians is much more indirect,
and here it is interesting how significant education is for students. The role
of the university, of certain courses, and of certain professors may be
noteworthy in their lives. That can be something which is pretty significant.
It may also be the case that they do something subsequently that takes them
very far away from what they did in the university, but it may also be the case
that the way they started thinking in the university engaged processes of
thought that may nonetheless play a role in what they do in life. I had in
class people who later worked on the stock market. Or there was one person, for
example, who flew a plane in the navy. These are people who continued to think about
things that didn’t really fit in with their own activities but on some level
still helped to shape their thought processes.” (242-243)
“The most prominent thing, I think, is the way
in which people with whom you work may go on themselves to be educators,
sometimes on university levels but not always, and they in a way continue to
transmit to other students not what you’ve told them but processes that they developed
during interactions with you and other people in classes.” (243)
Two comments on the interaction between
discourses of different disciplines:
“What always happens, which is to some extent
fortunate and to some extent unfortunate, is that certain kinds of discourses
tend to be developed, and once there is more conflict people within those
discourses tend to believe that they are under siege. And so they flock together
to help protect themselves against external pressures, and to some extent that
happens within deconstructive discourse, and poststructuralist discourse in
general, as well as psychoanalytic discourse, and the problem is that there may
be a decline in mutual cross-fertilization, in the kind of interaction that
those within the tendency and those outside the tendency see as challenging.”
(244)
“[…] I think the role of intellectual
historians is not simply to learn the discourses and be able to speak like
Foucault or Derrida, but to engage in a process of translation. There should be,
at least in intellectual history, a kind of translation going on between the
discourse that seems alien and the discourse that’s been developed as more or
less current within the historical field. History is often if not typically
very close to common sense, a commonsensical language. So there has to be a
kind of mutual give-and-take with interactive inflections made with respect to “ordinary”
or commonsensical language and the distinctive discourses or special languages
of critical theory. In this way problems seen as significant within the
discipline may be rethought in part through an appeal to discourses experienced
as alien by historians and in part as these “alien” or unfamiliar discourses
are affected by certain problems – including the problems studied in detail by
historians – so that critical-theoretical discourses don’t simply go their own way
by developing a very, very abstract, involuted orientation that is not affected
by certain problems that people in history or government or sociology see as
significant problems. There has to be that kind of mutual interaction, which is
always a form of translation with both the gains and losses of translation. In
a very broad sense these are issues that have both obvious political ramifications
and more subtle political ramifications in terms of the constitution of and
interactions among disciplines.” (244-245)
Again on the idea of history as a “dialogue”
with the past, now with an emphasis on the concept of “transference”:
“I would begin by pointing out that I have
never seen history (in the sense of historiography) only as an exchange or “dialogue”
with the past. I have also insisted that any exchange is tensely bound up with
reconstruction requiring research. So a dialogue is mediated and even checked
in multiple ways – by disciplinary protocols that are both constraining and enabling,
by exchanges with other inquirers investigating the same object or subject, and
by the results of research. It may also be limited or blocked by various forces
– differences in power, unconscious processes (including projective
tendencies), and the obscurity or opacity of the object.” (245)
“...by transference I mean primarily one’s
implication in the other or the object of study with the tendency to repeat in
one’s own discourse or practice tendencies active in, or projected into, the
other or object, for example, having a ritualistic, phobic response to ritual
or replicating a scapegoat mechanism in an analysis of scapegoating (say, with
respect to historians or other analysts who disagree with your approach). This dimension
of transference is, I think, less developed in the literature than the interpersonal
bond, which is often centered overmuch on the relation between psychoanalyst
and analysand. Transferential processes are most pronounced and difficult to
manage with respect to the most affectively charged or ‘cathected’ issues, for
example, topics such as the Holocaust, slavery, colonialism, or, until recently
in France, the French Revolution. I think that clinical, Oedipally centered
transference is best understood as a subcase of this broader tendency to
repeat.” (245-246) “Transference is related to a certain excess in relations
between self and other that calls for understanding and representation yet is not
fully open to mastery or knowledge. In this sense one cannot say exactly what
one means by transference if by “exactly” one means a definition or set of
criteria that provide adequate knowledge and a full grasp of the problems
involved. Such a definition of transference would eliminate the problem of
transference. One can only be as precise and comprehensive as the problems allow.
And one can call for greater reflection and self-reflection about them on the
part of those implicated in them – reflection that may revise, supplement, or contest
one’s own formulations.” (246)
Answering the question: “Is it possible to
apply psychoanalysis, which is a theory about the individual, to history, a field
of knowledge about the human collective, social life through time?” (246)
“I have been trying to argue that it is
possible, and I think that the belief that psychoanalysis is a theory about the
individual is itself dogmatic and open to question. I would argue that the
basic concepts of psychoanalysis, such as transference, repression, disavowal, acting-out
and working-through undercut the opposition between the individual and the
collective and are individuated or collectivized to varying degrees as they
apply in different contexts […]”. (247)
“It is rather to place in question a conception
of history that defines its own putative critical, secular rationality by
opposing itself to a homogeneous, indiscriminate, even phobic idea of memory as
its other. This deceptive conception of history effaces or denies the very
possibility both of a critically tested memory and of possibly fetishized
aspects of historiography itself (for example, a certain idea of the archive or
the document). In brief, I argue that history and memory are modes of
inscription that certainly should not be conflated, but neither should they
simply be opposed.” (247)
“Indeed one of the ways history is not merely
professional or a matter of research, which of course does not imply
denigrating research, is that it undertakes to create a critically tested,
accurate memory as its contribution to a cognitively and ethically responsible public
sphere.” (248)
On what is entailed by the deconstruction of
binary oppositions:
“One of the dubious understandings of
deconstruction itself, which has had an influence even on tendencies critical
of deconstruction, is the idea that the deconstruction of binary oppositions
necessarily entails the undoing or blurring of all distinctions. On the
contrary, I argue that the deconstruction of binaries, which is fruitful in
undoing the bases of a scapegoat mechanism and, more generally, in questioning overly
sharp boundaries, for example, between disciplines, does not entail a collapse
of all distinctions or a conception of all thought as entering into a gray zone
or an area of free play. Rather it poses in accentuated terms the problem of
elaborating distinctions in examining empirical reality or history, criticizing
the manner in which distinctions are often compulsively converted into
binaries, developing what one argues to be more desirable distinctions,
assessing their strength or weakness, and carefully exploring their relations
to what Derrida terms undecidability.” (249-250)
On the current state of the field:
“I would say that at the present time an
important concern is that intellectual and even cultural history may be in the
process of being de-institutionalized within the discipline of history.” (254)
“The elimination or down-sizing of
theoretically alert intellectual or cultural-intellectual historians from
departments of history would deprive the discipline of a certain leaven, and it
would impair the sustained critical interaction between theoretical reflection
and practices of research addressed to specific problems.” (254)